John Austin and Excuses

You said:

John Austin wrote about excuses and their implication for ethics. elaborate

ChatGPT said:

John L. Austin, the British philosopher of language and a leading figure in ordinary language philosophy, delivered a lecture titled “A Plea for Excuses” (1956), which explores the nuances of how people use language when offering excuses for their actions. While this work is grounded in philosophy of language, it has significant ethical implications—especially for understanding responsibility, intention, and moral evaluation.

Here’s a detailed elaboration:


1. Austin’s Aim: Analyzing Ordinary Language

Austin’s primary aim in “A Plea for Excuses” is to show that careful attention to the way we use language—particularly in ordinary, everyday situations—reveals important distinctions that are philosophically significant. He challenges abstract moral theories that ignore how people actually talk and reason about moral behavior.


2. Excuses vs. Justifications

Austin distinguishes between:

  • Justifications: You admit the act, but deny it was wrong (e.g., “I hit him, but it was in self-defense”).
  • Excuses: You admit the act was wrong, but claim your culpability is reduced (e.g., “I was drunk,” “I didn’t know”).

This distinction is ethically important because it reflects different types of moral responsibility. A justification challenges the wrongness of the act; an excuse concedes that, but questions the degree of blame.


3. The Complexity of Moral Concepts

Austin emphasizes that our moral and legal language is finely grained—terms like accidentally, inadvertently, by mistake, under duress, etc., are not synonyms. They track subtle differences in intention, knowledge, and control, all of which are relevant to moral judgment.

His work thus supports an ethics of attention to particulars, not abstract rules.


4. Ethical Implications: Responsibility and Blame

Austin’s analysis helps clarify:

  • Degrees of responsibility: Some acts are less blameworthy due to mitigating circumstances.
  • Moral luck: Two people may attempt the same act, but one fails (e.g., attempted vs. successful harm)—does that affect their blameworthiness?
  • Intent vs. Outcome: Language around excuses shows that we often care more about intentions than merely consequences.

5. Against Moral Rigidity

Austin’s method undermines overly rigid ethical systems by showing that real moral judgment depends on contextual, linguistic, and psychological subtleties. His plea is a defense of moral realism grounded in lived experience and speech—not abstract theorizing.


6. Legacy: Influence on Ethics and Law

Austin’s attention to the nuances of excuse language influenced later work in:

  • Legal theory: How courts treat mitigating circumstances.
  • Moral philosophy: Discussions of agency, voluntariness, and responsibility.
  • Analytic ethics: Philosophers like Bernard Williams and Judith Jarvis Thomson follow this “thick description” approach.

Summary

John Austin’s “A Plea for Excuses” is not just about words—it is about how language encodes moral life. Excuses reveal how we parse intention, blame, control, and character in ethically complex situations. His work encourages a situational, linguistically informed ethics, where moral evaluation depends on how people understand and describe what they have done.

Would you like a breakdown of specific examples Austin uses, or how this contrasts with Kantian or utilitarian ethics?

You said:

yes

ChatGPT said:

Great — let’s do a breakdown in two parts:


1. Specific Examples Austin Uses

In “A Plea for Excuses”, Austin doesn’t focus on grand ethical dilemmas but rather on everyday cases where people explain or defend their actions. These cases show how we sort out moral and legal responsibility in real life.

A. “I didn’t do it intentionally.”

  • Case: Someone spills coffee on another person’s notes.
  • Excuse: “I didn’t do it on purpose.”
  • Philosophical use: This differentiates an accident from an intentional act, which has moral and legal consequences.

B. “I did it by mistake.”

  • Case: A secretary sends a letter to the wrong recipient.
  • Excuse: “I sent it by mistake.”
  • Austin’s point: There’s a difference between being careless, being misinformed, or having misjudged the situation. Language like “by mistake” or “by accident” refers to different kinds of fault, and each can carry different ethical weight.

C. “I was forced to.” / “I had no choice.”

  • Case: Someone signs a document under threat.
  • Excuse: “I was under duress.”
  • Ethical implication: This invokes a lack of voluntariness, which can mitigate or even eliminate moral blame.

These are not just verbal maneuvers; they map real moral distinctions. Austin’s method shows that language already contains ethical theory, if we pay close enough attention.


2. Contrast with Kantian and Utilitarian Ethics

A. Kantian Ethics

  • Kant: Morality is based on rational duty. The only thing that counts is whether you acted out of respect for the moral law (the categorical imperative).
  • Excuses in Kantian view: Largely irrelevant unless they show the act wasn’t truly willed. If you act wrongly but with a good will, you’re still morally worthy.
  • Austin’s contrast: He sees our ordinary moral judgments as more flexible. We evaluate excuses even when duties are clear, because we live in a world of complexity, not idealized rational agents.

Austin would likely say that Kantian ethics ignores the richness of our moral vocabulary—and with it, the reality of our moral life.


B. Utilitarian Ethics

  • Utilitarianism: What matters is the outcome—maximizing happiness or minimizing harm.
  • Excuses in utilitarian view: They matter only insofar as they predict or explain consequences. If a lie led to better results, it’s justified.
  • Austin’s contrast: He notes that we sometimes excuse bad outcomes if the agent had good intentions, or blame people even when the outcome was fine—because we also care about character, effort, norms, etc.

Austin’s approach defends the idea that how and why someone did something matters, not just what resulted.


Summary of the Contrasts

FeatureAustin (Ordinary Language)Kantian EthicsUtilitarian Ethics
FocusNuances of action, intention, responsibilityUniversal moral duty & willOutcomes & consequences
MethodLinguistic analysis of excusesRational moral lawCost-benefit calculation
View of ExcusesImportant, context-sensitiveMorally secondary unless they negate willOnly relevant if they affect results
Ethics of Everyday LifeCentralAbstractedOften sidestepped

Leave a Reply

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.