Chapter 19 of his History is about Jean Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) who is known primarily for his essays, as collected in , The Social Contract and Discourses, translated with an introduction by G.D.H. Cole, 1913. [(In my American edition of 1950, there is an 1931 entry in the Bibliography. ]
Some regard Rousseau as the greatest political philosopher. Here are two such opinions;
“. . . Jean-Jacques Rousseau is the greatest political philosopher who has ever lived. His claim to immortality rests upon one short book, Of the Social Contract . . .” Robert Paul Wolff, About Philosophy 9th ed. (2006), p. 318.
G. D. H, Cole (1889-1959), in his clear and insightful introduction to Rousseau’s essays, writes: “. . . the Social Contract itself is by far the best of all textbooks of political philosophy.” (p. l)
Bertrand Russell, on the other hand, describes Rousseau in the most disparaging ways. Let me cite the most outrageous of his claims:
1. “. . . the inventor of the political philosophy of pseudo-democratic dictatorship as opposed to traditional absolute monarchies.”
2. “Hitler is an outcome of Rousseau; Roosevelt and Churchill of Locke.”
3. “Rousseau forgets his romanticism and speaks like a sophistical policeman. Hegel, who owed much to Rousseau, adopted his misuse of the word “freedom,” and defined it as the right to obey the police, or something not very different.”
4. “Its doctrines, though they pay lip-service to democracy, tend to the justification of the totalitarian State.”
5. The final paragraph of Russell’s chapter on Rousseau is this:
“The Social Contract became the Bible of most of the leaders in the French Revolution, but no doubt, as is the fate of Bibles, it was not carefully read and was still less understood by many of its disciples. It introduced the habit of metaphysical abstractions among the theorists of democracy, and by its doctrine of the general will it made possible the mystic identification of a leader with its people, which has no need of confirmation by so mundane an application as the ballot-box, Much of its philosophy could be appropriated by Hegel. [Hegel selects for special praise the distinction between the general will and the will of all. He says: “Rousseau would have made a sounder contribution towards a theory of the State, if he had always kept the distinction in mind.” (Logic, Sec. 163).] in his defense of the Prussian autocracy. Its first-fruit in practice was the reign of Robespierre, the dictatorship of Russia and Germany (especially the latter) are in part an outcome of Rousseau’s teaching. What further triumphs the future has to offer to his ghost I do not venture to predict.”
I find all these claims bizarre — a complete misunderstanding of Rousseau.
As an immediate antidote to this misreading, I recommend the introduction to the essays by G.D.H. Cole, and an essay which Cole recommended as a historical summary of the social contract tradition by D.G. Ritchie, “Chapter 7. Contributions to the History of the Social Contract Theory,” (pp. 196-226) in Darwin and Hegel with Other Philosophical Studies (1893)
Although in my opinion Russell totally misunderstood Rousseau’s Social Contract, for the sake of what I am about to say, let us assume (pretend) that Russell’s interpretation of Rousseau is correct. Let us assume (pretend) that Rousseau was espousing a dictatorship of a leader. How does such an alleged espousal lead to, cause, influence, or inspire Hitler?
To make such a claim at least plausible would require, I think, the following presuppositions:
1. Intellectuals have an influence on the general public, or
2. Intellectuals have an influence on politicians, or
3. Hitler was influenced by Rousseau.
My general view is that intellectuals are taken notice of by mostly other intellectuals, and hardly at all by the general public or by politicians. This is to say that intellectuals have almost no effect on politics.
The exceptions are — to speak sarcastically — philosopher kings, i.e., politicians who happen to be intellectuals. I am thinking of such figures as Jefferson, Madison, Hamilton, Woodrow Wilson (in the United States); Thomas Masaryk in Czechoslovakia; Lenin and Trotsky in Russia; and such.
Was Hitler an intellectual? And if he read Rousseau, what did he get from him? How in the world does one support the thesis that Hitler is an outcome of Rousseau?
Looking on the Internet whether anyone else commented on Russell’s view of Rousseau, I came across the following interesting piece: Thomas Riggins, “Russell, Rousseau, And Rationality: A Marxist Critique,” Countercurrents.org, June 30, 2007.
ChatGPT:
This critique of Bertrand Russell’s interpretation of Jean-Jacques Rousseau — particularly from History of Western Philosophy — raises significant philosophical and historiographical concerns. Let’s evaluate the argument and context more closely, focusing on fairness, accuracy, and rhetorical tone.
1. Russell’s View of Rousseau: An Overview
In History of Western Philosophy (1945), Russell indeed delivers a sharply critical portrait of Rousseau. He attributes to Rousseau the philosophical underpinnings of what he calls “pseudo-democratic dictatorship,” effectively tying Rousseau to totalitarianism and authoritarianism — especially as later manifested in figures like Robespierre, Hegel, and even Hitler.
Russell’s Claims:
- Rousseau is the “inventor of the political philosophy of pseudo-democratic dictatorship.”
- Hitler is an outcome of Rousseau, whereas Locke leads to Roosevelt and Churchill.
- Rousseau misuses concepts like freedom, echoing later distortions by Hegel.
These remarks are polemical and reductive. They reflect Russell’s 20th-century anxieties (post-WWII), particularly about totalitarian regimes, and his preference for liberal individualism over collectivist or romantic ideologies.
2. Is Russell Being Fair to Rousseau?
Russell’s view is widely seen as an oversimplification. Rousseau’s writings, especially The Social Contract, are undeniably complex and often internally contradictory. However, labeling him as a proto-totalitarian ignores several core ideas Rousseau actually defended:
- Popular sovereignty and participatory democracy.
- A profound concern with freedom as autonomy — the notion that true freedom means obedience to laws one has a hand in making.
- Critique of inequality and privilege, anticipating social justice discourse.
It’s true Rousseau’s idea that individuals must sometimes be “forced to be free” has authoritarian implications. But that line has often been taken out of context. Rousseau’s goal was not dictatorship, but a deeply moral and collective form of self-governance. Equating that directly with Hitler’s fascism is a stretch — historically and philosophically.
3. The Counterpoint: Rousseau as the Greatest Political Philosopher
Citing Robert Paul Wolff and G.D.H. Cole, the author of the critique emphasizes that Rousseau is, to many, among the most profound thinkers of liberty, equality, and democratic theory. Cole, in particular, sees The Social Contract as a definitive political text.
This shows a divide:
- Russell’s liberal, Enlightenment-derived empiricism values reason, individualism, and institutional moderation.
- Rousseau’s romantic and moral philosophy is rooted in emotion, virtue, and collective will — ideas more susceptible to radical political interpretations.
But to claim Rousseau “caused” Hitler is not just analytically poor, it’s historically naive. Rousseau was appropriated by very different thinkers, sometimes against the grain of his philosophy. The same can be said for Nietzsche.
4. Escaping from Bullshit?
The original writer frames Russell’s interpretation as “bullshit” — likely invoking Harry Frankfurt’s definition: speech that is indifferent to truth, more concerned with persuasion or posturing than accuracy.
That’s a provocative but defensible charge:
- Russell may be using rhetorical hyperbole to fit Rousseau into a historical narrative of dangerous ideas.
- This move may prioritize dramatic impact over scholarly fairness.
However, Russell wasn’t writing an academic monograph; History of Western Philosophy was written during wartime exile and meant for a general audience. His intent was to provoke thought, not always to provide comprehensive or balanced analysis.
Conclusion: Russell’s Critique is Insightful but Flawed
Russell’s History remains valuable — but as a starting point, not a final judgment. His depiction of Rousseau:
- Reflects his political biases (liberal rationalism).
- Is historically selective and rhetorically exaggerated.
- Misses Rousseau’s moral complexity and democratic commitments.
Calling Russell’s take “bullshit” may be harsh, but it rightly signals a need to critically interrogate even our intellectual heroes. As the author suggests: “everything is subject to critical review.”
Would you like a comparison chart showing how Locke, Rousseau, Hegel, and Russell differ on key political concepts?
You said:
YES
ChatGPT said:
Great — here’s a comparison chart highlighting the key differences and continuities among John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, G.W.F. Hegel, and Bertrand Russell on core political and philosophical concepts:
Political Philosophy Comparison Chart
Concept | John Locke (1632–1704) | Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778) | G.W.F. Hegel (1770–1831) | Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) |
---|---|---|---|---|
Human Nature | Rational, cooperative, self-interested | Born good, corrupted by society | Evolving self-consciousness; Spirit unfolding in history | Mostly rational, but driven by logic & scientific reason |
State of Nature | Peaceful, with natural rights | Free and equal, but not moral or social | Abstract; pre-historical concept in self-development | Uses as a logical abstraction in critique of others |
Government’s Role | Protect life, liberty, and property | Realize the “general will” through direct democracy | Embody ethical life (Sittlichkeit) in the rational state | Defend liberal democracy, protect individual rights |
Freedom | Absence of coercion; individual liberty | Obedience to laws one has helped make (“forced to be free”) | Freedom = recognition in and through social institutions | Classical liberal view; autonomy of individual reason |
View on Democracy | Representative democracy is ideal | Participatory/direct democracy is essential | Constitutional monarchy; rational state as democracy | Strong supporter of democracy; skeptical of dogmas |
Property | Natural right; tied to labor | Origin of inequality; not natural | Property as social institution within ethical life | Supportive but cautious of capitalism’s moral limits |
View on Revolution | Justified if rights are violated | Necessary to restore freedom and equality | Historical necessity in dialectical progression | Supported some revolutions, opposed authoritarianism |
Religion and Politics | Separation of church and state | Civil religion needed to unify citizens | Religion is part of Spirit’s self-realization | Strong secularist; critical of organized religion |
Relation to Totalitarianism (per Russell) | Antidote — individual liberty as safeguard | Proto-totalitarian (in Russell’s view) | Philosophical root of state worship | Opposes all forms of authoritarianism, links Rousseau & Hegel to it |
Legacy | Liberalism, U.S. Constitution | Romanticism, radical democracy, French Revolution | German idealism, Marx, modern state theory | Analytic philosophy, anti-authoritarian liberalism |
Key Notes:
- Russell’s criticisms of Rousseau and Hegel come from his deep fear of collectivist ideologies and state worship, especially after WWII.
- However, Rousseau’s “general will” is not inherently totalitarian — it depends on whether it’s interpreted as majoritarian imposition or collective self-rule.
- Locke and Russell share more in their liberal foundations, though Russell was a more secular, scientifically-minded thinker.
- Hegel is the most difficult of the four and most controversial — his ideas were later interpreted (or misinterpreted) by both Marxists and nationalists.
Would you like a visual timeline or infographic-style version of this chart?