C. D. Broad, Review of An Examination of the Place of Reason in Ethics by S. E. Toulmin, Mind, New Series, Vol. 61, No. 241 (Jan., 1952), pp. 93-101. VI -- CRITICAL NOTICES An Examination of the Place of Reason in Ethics. By S. E. Toulmin. Cambridge : University Press. Pp. xiv + 228. It is easy to state Mr. Toulmin's main problem and to formulate in general terms his attempted solution of it, but when one comes to details there are things in his book which I find obscure and puzzling. I will therefore begin with what is clear to me, and will then raise some questions about the parts which I do not fully understand. The main problem may be put as follows. In the course of our private reflections and our discussions with others we seem prima facie to be constantly offering factual propositions as reasons for or against moral conclusions. Moreover, we constantly talk as if some of these reasons were valid and others were invalid for the purpose for which they are adduced. Thus, e.g., a person might assert that he is under an obligation to pay a certain sum of money to another to-morrow, on the ground that he has borrowed that sum from him and that to-morrow is the agreed date for repayment. Another person might allege that he is under an obligation to challenge a certain man to a duel, because the latter has publicly insulted him. Most civilized men would consider the former to be a valid reason and most contemporary Englishmen would consider the latter to be an invalid one. Mr. Toulmin argues that such prima facie appearances must be accepted at their face-value, and his main problem is to determine what kind of factual premisses are valid reasons for moral conclusions. In Chapter X Mr. Toulmin considers what kind of reasons (whether valid or invalid in particular cases) are regarded as relevant to specifically moral questions. He develops his answer further in Chapter XI. His conclusions may be summarized as follows.
It would appear from the above that Mr. Toulmin's answer to his question is a form of a very old and highly respectable ethical theory, viz., hedonistic utilitarianism. There is little, if anything, in it with which Sidgwick, e.g., would have quarrelled, though Sidgwick argues his case with enormously greater detail and sublety, and combines it with the acceptance of certain very abstract principles of distribution which he regards as self-evident and does not attempt to base on utilitarian considerations. Notwithstanding the passages which I have quoted, which seem to support this interpretation, there are others which seem to suggest a different view. Thus, in Chapter X Mr. Toulmin says that morality never becomes wholly teleological, and states as his reason that the code current in a given society remains obligatory on its members in all cases in regard to which it is unambiguous. He reverts to this point in Chapter XI. So far, he says, he has been considering only the question : How do we in fact profess to distinguish valid from invalid reasoning in moral questions? He now raises the question: What makes some such reasoning valid and some invalid? I take it that this should mean: Can one explain satisfactorily why the arguments which pass these tests are valid and why those which fail to do so are invalid? From what Mr. Toulmin says in other parts of his book about similar questions which have been raised about the types of reasoning commonly accepted as valid by scientists in scientific reasoning I conclude that his answer would be that such a question is improper and meaningless. But what he actually discusses here is whether we can reasonably ask for a single test for the validity of moral reasoning, which shall apply to all the three cases which he has distinguished. This is obviously a different question. Nor does he discuss even this directly. Instead he asks whether either of the two tests which he has mentioned could be dispensed with in favour of the other. This again would seem to be a different question. Mr. Toulmin's answer to it is as follows. If we adopt conformity to a current moral code alone as our test, we shall never be able to question the rightness of any such code. In that case 'morality' will collapse into mere 'authority'. If, on the other hand, we adopt the utilitarian test alone, 'morality' will collapse into mere 'expediency'. Now we use the words 'moral' and 'morality' in such a way that neither arguments from mere authority nor arguments from mere expediency count as moral. I should have thought that the utilitarian, at any rate, had an easy answer to this, and that Mr. Toulmin had in effect given it in other parts of his book which I have already quoted. The utilitarian would agree that, as a matter of fact, the feeling of obligation is directly attached to acts which accord with the moral code accepted in one's community, and that it is not in general mediated by any thought of utility. He could argue very plausibly that it is of the utmost utility that this should be so. But he would say that the only ultimately valid reason for the principles of any moral code is their general utility; and that the only valid reason for obeying them in particular cases where disobedience would have greater first-order utility than obedience is the various kinds of second-order disutility which arises from any breach of a generally accepted and generally useful set of rules. Now, there are certain well-known theories as to the correct analysis of what I will call 'moral indicatives' which would seem to allow no place for reasoning in moral topics. Mr. Toulmin discusses the two main types of such theories under the titles of 'the Subjective Approach' and 'the Imperative Approach'. The subjectivist allows that moral indicatives do, as their grammatical form suggests, express judgments about actions, intentions, motives, etc. But he alleges that what a person who makes such a judgment is asserting in any case is simply that the action in question evokes in him, or in some class of persons of which he is a member, a certain kind of emotional reaction towards it. It is obvious that on this view there can be no question of presenting reasons, valid or invalid, for or against a person's moral judgments. It is alleged by subjectivists that what are called 'arguments' on moral questions are really certain psychological techniques for altering men's emotional reactions. Since no question of truth or falsity can enter here, the subjectivist denies that we can talk of 'validity' or 'invalidity' in any literal sense. What a person calls a 'valid' type of moral argument is simply a technique for altering emotional attitudes, which happens to appeal to him. I do not know that there is any way of answering such contentions except by pointing out that they are not in accord with common-sense and common usage and by asserting that the latter have a prima facie claim to acceptance. This, at any rate, is all the answer that Mr. Toulmin gives. His counter-assertions amount to the following.
Mr. Toulmin gives the name ' imperativist' to those who hold that moral indicatives do not express judgments of any kind, but do serve to evince certain emotions or desires of the speaker and to evoke certain emotions or stimulate certain actions in his hearers. In discussing this type of theory he confines himself to the doctrine that moral indicatives express, in a grammatically misleading form, what would be more correctly expressed by uttering a sentence in the imperative. Now, as he admits, there is no doubt a perfectly good sense of 'reason' in which one can ask: 'What was X's reason for giving that order?' or 'What reason is there why Y should obey that order of X's?' But 'reason' here means motive for or against acting in a certain way, whilst Mr. Toulmin is concerned with 'reason' in the sense of ground for accepting something as true or rejecting it as false. In that sense it is plainly nonsensical to talk of reasons for or against a command, since the alternatives 'true' and 'false' do not apply to it. Now it seems to him to be a plain fact that in moral contexts we do give reasons, in the sense of grounds for accepting as true or rejecting as false, and that we do distinguish between those which are valid and those which are invalid. He concludes therefore that the imperativist analysis of moral indicatives cannot be correct. There remains a third well-known analysis of moral indicatives, which Mr. Toulmin discusses elaborately and rejects. This is the doctrine that such sentences express judgments to the effect that an action or an experience, etc., has one or another of certain objective properties, of which such words as 'morally right', 'morally good', etc., are names. Mr. Toulmin begins by distinguishing three types of property, viz., simple, complex, and scientific qualities. Both simple and complex qualities are 'directly perceivable'. A simple quality cannot be defined without circularity either in terms of simpler qualities or in terms of any standard set of operations. An example would be yellow, in the sense in which it is mentioned in the sentence: 'That looks yellow to me from here now'. A complex quality can be defined in terms of a certain standard operation, e.g., counting, which must be gone through before it can safely be asserted or denied of a perceived object. An example would be the property of being heptagonal. A scientific quality is one which cannot be perceived directly and may not be perceptible at all, but whose presence or absence is detected by a certain standard operation. An example would be yellow, in the sense in which it is mentioned in the sentence: 'The sun is really yellow, though it appears red at sunset'. Mr. Toulmin asserts that all properties fall under one or other of these three headings. He also asserts that this is true too of psychological properties, such as 'haughty' and 'meek'. (I do not see how this can possibly be so, unless 'perception' is extended to cover introspection.) He concludes that anyone who alleges that goodness, e.g., is a property of the entities which are called 'good', must be asserting that it is a quality which falls into one or other of these three classes. He then tries to show that goodness, rightness, etc., cannot be directly perceived qualities, whether simple or complex. Unless I am mistaken, he does not discuss the alternative that they are 'scientific qualities'. The course of his argument appears to be as follows.
What are we to say of this argument? (1) It is of the same verbal form as the following argument. Every regular solid must be either a tetrahedron or a cube or an octahedron or a dodecahedron or an icosahedron. This has neither of these shapes. Therefore this cannot be a regular solid. But there is an important difference. The premiss in the above argument is a necessary consequence of the agreed definition of 'regular solid' and the axioms of Euclid; it is not a mere assertion about the sense in which the word 'regular solid' is commonly used. The corresponding premiss in Mr. Toulmin's argument is admittedly a mere assertion as to the way in which the word 'property' is commonly used. In. such a case one is inclined to suspect that the exhaustive set of alternatives has been chosen by the author in such a way as to exclude the proposition which he wishes to reject. It is rejection by verbal legislation, and it is unlikely to appeal to any but the already converted. (2) If the phrase 'organic defect' in one of Mr. Toulmin's alternative sources of difference is taken literally, it is irrelevant to the case of 'good' or 'right'; for no-one supposes that these are names of qualities which are literally perceptible by any of our senses or by any conceivable extension of them. But, if it is interpreted more widely, the objectivist would be likely to say that,, when all other sources of difference between A and B have been eliminated, the conflict between their moral judgments must arise from a moral cognitive defect analogous to colour-blindness, which he would describe as 'moral blindness' or 'moral insensitiveness'. It is plain that Mr. Toulmin has the second of these contentions in mind in the argument which he uses on pp. 23 to 25. He imagines the case of a person who habitually exhibits good moral qualities, performs right actions, and gives what are admittedly valid moral reasons for doing them. He imagines such a person being asked whether, when considering what he ought to do, he is aware of any 'non-natural property of fittingness' in the alternative which he decides to enact. The person is supposed to answer that he does not, that he decides to enact a certain alternative because there is a valid moral reason for doing so, and that he is not interested in any additional 'non-natural property' of the alternative. Mr. Toulmin asserts that the objectivist would have to say of such a man that he may know what things are good but cannot know what goodness is, and that he is like a colour-blind man who has learned a technique for distinguishing red things from green ones but is missing an essential experience. This, Mr. Toulmin thinks, would be ridiculous. The reason that he gives is that we use the phrase 'to know what goodness is' in such a way that it is equivalent to 'being virtuous and upright and giving good reasons for one's actions'. I should doubt whether this argument will produce much impression on those to whom it is addressed. In the first place, they might legitimately object that the supposed virtuous person is a puppet of Mr. Toulmin's creation, whose answer is put into his mouth by his maker. We may safely assume that no Gallup poll has ever been taken of the answers of virtuous persons to Mr. Toulmin's question. Secondly, it might be objected that a plain man, however virtuous, could hardly be expected to return any very reliable answer to a question put to him in technical philosophical terminology ('non-natural properties') which is unfamiliar to him. Mr. Toulmin alleges, not only that the objectivist account of moral indicatives is false, but also that it prevents those who hold it from paying adequate attention to the question which most interests him, viz., the question of valid and invalid reasons for moral judgments. This is an historical statement against which, I should have thought, there is plenty of evidence. I suppose that Sidgwick and Moore and Ross may fairly be cited as distinguished exponents of the objectivist doctrine. None of them has neglected to discuss seriously the questions: 'What makes right acts right?' and 'What makes good things good?' But surely this is the form which Mr. Toulmin's question about valid and invalid reasons in morals takes, when formulated in terms of an objectivist view of the nature of moral indicatives. Much more valuable than Mr. Toulmin's detailed arguments against the subjectivist, the imperativist, and the objectivist accounts of moral indicatives is his own estimate of the strong and the weak points in each of them and of the places of each in a correct and adequate account of moral phenomena. Leaving aside for the moment certain features which I find obscure. I think that his main points may fairly be summarized as follows.
I find myself in general agreement with much in Mr. Toulmin's position as thus summarized. What I do not clearly understand is his own positive account of what is expressed by moral indicatives. One aspect of this is stated in Chapter VI under the heading 'Gerundive Concepts'. These concepts fall under the general formula 'worthy to be treated in a certain way'. Thus a 'true proposition' is one which is worthy to be believed, a 'valid argument' is one which is worthy to be accepted as making its conclusion worthy to be believed, a 'beautiful object' is one which is worthy to be admired aesthetically, a 'morally good disposition' is one which is worthy of moral approval, and a 'morally right alternative' is one which is worthy to be chosen for enactment. Mr. Toulmin states definitely that gerundive concepts cannot be identified with or defined wholly in terms of de facto subjective attitudes. To think that they can is the typical 'naturalistic fallacy'. There is nothing particularly new or startling in this aspect of the theory. It has been very fully developed by, e.g., Sir W. D. Ross and by Dr. Ewing. 'Worthiness to be treated in a certain way' is in fact our old friend 'fittingness', and, as such, I have no quarrel with it. The other aspect of Mr. Toulmin's theory is the identification of 'x is worthy of approval' with f there is a valid reason for approving x'; and the repeated assertion that logical conflict as to the goodness of x or the rightness of y reduces to conflict as to the validity of alleged reasons for approving x or for doing y as the case may be. Now this raises the following question. Does 'approving x' mean 'feeling a certain kind of emotion towards x' or 'judging that x is a worthy object of a certain kind of emotion'? On the first alternative the words 'valid reason' in the phrase 'valid reason for approving x' cannot be used in the sense in which they are used in the phrase 'valid reason for accepting so-and-so as true or rejecting it as false'. Yet it seemed to be an essential part of Mr. Toulmin's case against the view that moral 'arguments' are only a psychological method of altering or confirming men's emotional attitudes that such 'arguments' present 'reasons' in the sense of grounds for accepting something as true or rejecting it as false. Suppose, on the other hand, that we take 'approving x' to mean 'judging that x is a worthy object of a certain kind of emotion'. Then, no doubt, 'reasons' can be taken to mean 'grounds for accepting as true or rejecting as false'. But in that case I do not see how a conflict between 'x is good' and 'x is not good' can possibly reduce to a conflict as to the validity of the reasons alleged for approving x. Surely the conflict will be simply as to whether x is or is not a worthy object of a certain kind of emotion or not. It might be so, even though the alleged reasons for believing it to be so were invalid. And, whether they are valid or not, the question of their validity or invalidity is one thing, and the question whether the conclusion for which they are adduced is true or false is another. In conclusion I must mention that quite a considerable proportion of Mr. Toulmin's book is taken up with discussions about the nature of reasoning and explanation in natural science, about the distinction between 'appearance' and 'reality' there and in ordinary life, and so on. These parts of the book contain much interesting matter, but I must pass them over here. Their relevance is supposed to be this. They support the view that the nature and the criteria of moral reasoning must be ascertained by a direct study of such reasoning and of the contexts in which it occurs. They do so by pointing out that the same is true mutatis mutandis of non-moral reasoning in pure mathematics, in natural science, and in the affairs of daily life. C. D. Broad Cambridge University |